The methods
of theorizing in International relations can broadly be classified into two:
the classical approach and the scientific approach. The classical approach
draws on philosophy, history, tradition and law and impresses upon the ability
to employ keen judgment while theorizing, while the scientific approach places
confidence in logic, empirical procedures and mathematical proofs. The struggle
for supremacy between the two methodologies has led to tensions within the
discipline. Proponents of the classical approach, use of which can be traced
back to theorists such as Machiavelli and Morgenthau, have sought to negate the
efforts of those who advocate the relatively newer, scientific methodological
approach. Hedley Bull is one such scholar, who through his seven propositions
in “International Theory: The Case for a Classical Approach” has made his
distaste for the use of scientific methods in theorizing in the IR arena
abundantly clear.
The crux of
Bull’s argument is that by using scientific methods, theorists are at risk of
being reductionist. By restricting themselves to what can be logically or
empirically proven, scientific theorists are impinging upon their own capacity
to analyze and employ judgment. Bull also claims that most of the work done by
scientific theorists has its basis in the classical approach – i.e. it requires
analysis of history, philosophy and existing theories – and is redundant. Furthermore, he believes that the scientific approach oversimplifies and makes
generalizations that are unable to explain the moral phenomena in international relations.
Although I do not fully agree with Bull’s
unabashed criticism of the scientific approach to theorizing (a mixed method
approach seems most feasible, which will ensure ‘precision and rigor’ in
theorizing), an empirical or mathematical approach does indeed have many flaws.
First of all, creating a model on which to base and test hypotheses pertaining
to international relations can be problematic. According to Bull, there are an “unmanageable
number of variables”, each with their own assumptions and generalizations, used
to justify thoughts and ideas, which oversimplifies and complicates matters at
the same time. In addition, it is also difficult to ascertain results of tests
as perspectives and biases of theorists differ. Kenneth Waltz also has similar
reservations regarding the scientific approach: “Staring at the same set of
data, the parties to the debate came to sharply different conclusions, for the
images they entertained led them to select and interpret the data in different
ways”. In addition, it is imperative to keep in mind that global politics are
not static. World events have verified and falsified ideas and theories which have
subsequently led to the evolution of the discipline of IR, itself. Therefore,
it is difficult to fit events and relations between states into set criteria to
give credibility to a hypothesis or theory.
Although I
would like to commend Bull on how well structured and reader-friendly his
article was, I felt as if his cynicism only thinly veiled his outrage at the
prospect of theorists using the scientific approach gaining further ground and
credibility in the realm of international relations - at the expense of the classical
approach. “They see themselves as tough-minded and expert new men, taking over
and effete and woolly discipline, or pseudo discipline, which has so far
managed by some strange quirk to evade the scientific method but has always
been bound to succumb to it in the end”. While it was entertaining to read the article (rant) I do feel as if elaborating on the merits
of the scientific approach to theorizing might have helped balance out Bull’s
clear bias against the break from tradition.
Well written piece and I think this is a valid critique of Bull. You'll read subsequent analyses by scholars that take a more balanced approach. I enjoyed reading your analysis - keep up the good work!
ReplyDelete